top of page
Search

Too Much Inequality? Time to Move Toward Optimal Inequality?

Writer's picture: MetaEconGaryMetaEconGary

Updated: Nov 29, 2024

(Updated November 2024)


Krugman (2022) in the New York Times reminded me of what Adam Smith had to say about the matter of inequality, and, notice, I am talking here about inequality not redistribution. The problem is in the main a problem in pre-distribution, the lack of an empathy-based ethic giving reasoned balance up, down, and in the middle of the income ladder (see the opinion in the Substack on the need to bring John Rawls' philosophy back into play). Krugman (2022) also points to the Realtime Inequality simulator developed by Thomas Blanchet, Emmanuel Saez, Gabriel Zucman, Department of Economics, at the University of California- Berkeley. The inequality in the US is unprecedented, and, needs to be dealt with. Also see Krugman, 2023, on the "yacht indicator"... mega-yachts in vogue among the mega-rich, like in the Guilded Age: Time to bring back some version of The New Deal Order that tempered the excesses of that Age. It is time to seek an Optimal Inequality, as Dual Interest Theory in Metaeconomics makes clear.


It all reminded me to go back for another look at Rasmussen (2016b), who points to Adam Smith. As made clear in Rasmussen (2016a; 2016b), and, the point is also made in Lynne (2020, Chapters 7 and 14), that Adam Smith saw the need to deal with inequality in order to achieve happiness, peace (reduce the political economic chaos), and, yes, achieve economic efficiency. In thinking about income and wealth inequality, a look into what Adam Smith had in mind is revealed in the following quotes highlighted in Roberts (2014, p. 40), from The Theory of Moral Sentiments book, Smith (1759/1790):


What so great happiness as to be beloved, and to know that we deserve to be beloved? What so great misery as to be hated, and know we deserve to be hated?


Man naturally desires, not only to be loved, but to be lovely.


Using Dual Interest Theory (DIT) in Metaeconomics (Lynne 2020), first, to be beloved, one must avoid maximizing self-interest only on path 0G. Yet, to be beloved is served by being able to have a high income and, especially to be wealthy: People are generally in awe and otherwise display apparent love for people with high income, and especially the people who amass wealth, power, and influence. Scrooge is admired and loved for the acumen, the capability to have high income and make, and amass, wealth. Unfortunately, it can go too far, working to distort the sympathies (empathy with) favoring the people with high income and wealth, with disdain for the people with lower income and without wealth (Rasmussen 2016a, p. 342; 2016b; Sandel 2020).



Second, path 0G (and in the extreme of extremes, the vertical axis) is to be avoided, as it can lead to being hated. It is especially important to ensure that a person really deserves the income and wealth, relating to the need to be lovely. To be lovely was to temper the excesses on path 0G and operate more toward the shared other-interest path 0M. To be lovely --- and to deserve to be beloved --- is about being humane, as in contributing to a humane capitalism, a humane Market Forum, and, a humane Other Forum in both Community and Government. And as Adam Smith clarified, it was to be motivated from within, the conscience at work, a person doing it without someone outside driving it. Path 0M was to considered and something closer to it sought by each person, freely chosen.


Yet, in order to deal with inequality, sometimes Scrooge must be tempered (nudged) from the outside, by the Ghosts, nudging the conscience, representing something which the other (Cratchit, the Community) can go along with. Adam Smith fully understood how a person has a more primal tendency to operate too much on the arrogance of self-love, on self-interest only. And, when the nudging by the Ghosts fails, the Community as represented by Government may have to step in to temper the arrogance, temper (nudge if not outright regulation and control) the self-interest, to nudge paying higher wages (recognizing value V rather than always working to pay the survival price P in wages) and helping pay (tax T) substantively for the public goods. So, third, the matter is resolved --- peace (far less political chaos, a stable political economy), and happiness, as well as economic efficiency, all emerge --- on path 0Z, where one not only is a person beloved but deserving to be loved. And, intriguingly, economic efficiency on path 0Z requires substantive attention to value V and tax T, and not just price P: It is about good balance in the private & public-good, which also means finding the optimal inequality.


As the Roberts (2014) book would have it, How Adam Smith Can Change Your Life: An Unexpected Guide to Human Nature and Happiness, the guide is to temper the self-interest with doing the right thing, the good other-interest. The latter meant operating in the moral dimension, as sociologist Amitai Etzioni (1988) also identified, in The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics. Adam Smith not only understood what drove the making of wealth but the need to temper the making (and, especially the taking and keeping) process with the moral and ethical dimension.


It is summed up nicely by Ashraf, Camerer, and Loewenstein (2005, p. 142), pointing to Adam Smith as Behavioral Economist: “In short, Adam Smith’s world is not inhabited by dispassionate rational purely self-interested agents, but rather by multidimensional and realistic human beings.” Said multidimensional and realistic human beings also prefer optimal inequality, that which the other can go along with, i.e., that which fits in the ethical system giving context to making, taking, and keeping income and wealth.


And, especially important: Optimal inequality is not redistribution, but rather is a problem in pre-distribution. It is about paying higher wages and providing for more compensation over the entire spectrum of income and wealth, paid with less compensation and pay at the top. An especially obvious example comes from an ethics based look at CEO compensation. It is clear (empirical question which has been examined) that adequate incentive is in place for a CEO to bring talents into making a company more productive with something on the order of $30-40M in annual compensation. It is not necessary to provide $300-400M. Using the difference to make for higher pay at the bottom goes a long way to not only be adequately loved, but, to be lovely.


For a real world case in point, a case of pre-distribution in action, Dan Price, owner of Gravity Payments, cut a $1.1M annual draw on the company’s profits, and moved to a $70,000 minimum wage: See $70,000 Minimum Wage in the Metaeconomics Blog. The business has grown and prospered, as something more akin to value V --- what was actually being contributed, a kind of instrumental value V --- went to employees. In general, the massive wealth accumulated at the top by shareholders and owners of companies needs to be reduced, while still retaining adequate (but not extreme) incentives to make wealth. Providing for more reasonable (i.e., empathy based ethics reflecting the shared other-interest working to temper same) compensation over the entire spectrum of the labor and management levels of a company works far better in producing a humane capitalism. It may not have to be as drastic as in the Gravity Payments case, but it makes the point. Similar outcomes have been experienced in the pay and compensation in professional sports teams, like baseball and football. The highest performance (winning games, and happy players, fans) comes from keeping sufficient incentives at the top while not going to extremes in the difference in compensation.


And, again, a humane capitalism as envisioned by Adam Smith recognized the essential need to not only be loved (adequate incentives to make wealth) but also be lovely (everyone getting a reasonable piece of the action, not just the people at the top). So, also again, to emphasize: It is not about redistribution through higher tax T of people at the top, but rather ethical compensation across the whole spectrum, with people at the top who control the pay and compensation scales acting in empathy with the others. It is about tempering the excesses with empathy.


It is about empathy tempering ego, tempering the arrogance of self-love down to that which the other can go along with, like Adam Smith said it. Extreme greed is not extremely good for anyone, and, ironically, especially not for the extremely greedy: Scrooge, anyone? Scroogism (path 0G) does not work: Humane Capitalism (path 0Z) does, and, Adam Smith tried to teach us about it. It is about tempering the excesses with the sentiments, the empathy based ethics.


References


Ashraf, N., Camerer, C. F., and Lowenstein, G. . 2005. "Adam Smith, Behavioral Economist." Journal of Economic Perspectives 19 (3): 131-145.

Etzioni, Amitai. 1988. The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics. New York: Free Press.

Lynne, Gary D. 2020. Metaeconomics: Tempering Excessive Greed. Palgrave Advances in Behavioral Economics, John Tomer ed. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Rasmussen, Dennis C. 2016a. "Adam Smith on What is Wrong With Income Inequality." American Political Science Review 110 (2): 342-352.

Rasmussen, Dennis C. 2016b. “The Problem With Inequality, According to Adam Smith.” The Atlantic, June 9.

Roberts, R. 2014. How Adam Smith Can Change Your Life: An Unexpected Guide to Human Nature and Happiness. New York: Portfolio/Penguin.

Sandel, M. J. . 2020. The Tyranny of Merit: What's Become of the Common Good? Kindle ed. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

Smith, A. 1759/1790. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Introduction by Herbert W. Schneider digireads.com.

1,196 views1 comment

1件のコメント


picklegirl45
picklegirl45
2022年2月08日

Makes sense, that focusing on finding optimal inequality might play better than thinking about collecting taxes and redistributing income.

いいね!
bottom of page